Moral patienthood

Moral patienthood[1] (also called moral patience,[2] moral patiency,[3] moral status[4][5], and moral considerability[6]) is the state of being eligible for moral consideration by a moral agent.[4] In other words, the morality of an action depends at least partly on how it affects those beings that possess moral patienthood, which are called moral patients[7] or morally considerable beings.[6]

Notions of moral patienthood in non-human animals[8][9] and artificial entities[10][11] have been academically explored. More detail on the ethical treatment of nonhuman animals, specifically, can be seen at the Animal rights article.

Definition

Most authors define moral patients as "beings that are appropriate objects of direct moral concern".[4] This category may include moral agents, and usually does include them. For instance, Charles Taliaferro says: "A moral agent is someone who can bring about events in ways that are praiseworthy or subject to blame. A moral patient is someone who can be morally mistreated. All moral agents are moral patients, but not all moral patients (human babies, some nonhuman animals) are moral agents."[12]

Narrow usage

Some authors use the term in a more narrow sense, according to which moral patients are "beings who are appropriate objects of direct moral concern but are not (also) moral agents".[4] Tom Regan's The Case for Animal Rights used the term in this narrow sense.[13] This usage was shared by other authors who cited Regan, such as Nicholas Bunnin and Jiyuan Yu's Blackwell Dictionary of Western Philosophy,[13] Dinesh Wadiwel's The War Against Animals,[14] and the Encyclopedia of Population.[15] These authors did not think that moral agents are not eligible for moral consideration, they simply had a different view on how a "moral patient" is defined.

Relationship with moral agency

The paper by Luciano Floridi and J.W. Sanders, On the Morality of Artificial Agents, defines moral agents as "all entities that can in principle qualify as sources of moral action", and defines moral patients, in accordance with the common usage, as "all entities that can in principle qualify as receivers of moral action".[16] However, they note that besides inclusion of agents within patients, other relationships of moral patienthood with moral agency are possible. Marian Quigley's Encyclopedia of Information Ethics and Security summarizes the possibilities that they gave:

How can we characterize the relationship between ethical agents and patients? According to Floridi and Sanders (2004), there are five logical relationships between the class of ethical agents and the class of patients: (1) agents and patients are disjoint, (2) patients can be a proper subset of agents, (3) agents and patients can intersect, (4) agents and patients can be equal, or (5) agents can be a proper subset of patients. Medical ethics, bioethics, and environmental ethics "typify" agents and patients when the patient is specified as any form of life. Animals, for example, can be moral patients but not moral agents. Also, there are ethics that typify moral agenthood to include legal entities (especially human-based entities) such as companies, agencies, and artificial agents, in addition to humans.[17]

Mireille Hildebrandt notes that Floridi and Sanders, in their paper, spoke of "damage" instead of "harm", and that in doing so, they "avoid the usual assumption that an entity must be sentient to count as a patient."[18]

Implications

Moral patienthood (or full moral patienthood, in theories which allow for partial moral status) has been alleged (by the cited sources) to imply the following moral obligations:[5]

  • Stringent presumption against interference: Moral patienthood provides an extremely strong moral reason not to interfere (kill, experiment on, directly cause suffering of) beings that have it; may be overridden only in narrow circumstances.[19][20][21]
  • Strong reason to aid: Moral patienthood provides a comparably strong (but weaker than the presumption against interference) reason to provide aid to beings that have it; more easily overridden and does not usually silence other considerations.[22][23][24]
  • Strong reason to treat fairly: Comparable interests of moral patients matter equally in distributional choices; gives rise to strong reasons to treat such beings fairly (e.g., equal distribution when appropriate).[25][22]

Moral patienthood is, by itself, an independent reason to have these moral obligations; there may be other reasons to have these obligations, but merely having these obligations towards a being does not imply that the being is a moral patient.[5] (For instance, supposing that there is a moral obligation to keep promises, someone may acquire these moral obligations toward any being by simply promising to treat it like a moral patient.)

Grounds of moral patienthood

Moral patienthood has been claimed, in the literature, to be grounded in various properties.[5][26]

Property Definition Sources
Sophisticated cognitive capacities Moral patienthood is grounded in very sophisticated intellectual/emotional capacities (e.g., autonomy, self-awareness, valuing, caring). Kant (Groundwork)[27]; Quinn[24]; McMahan[20]; Tooley[28]; Singer[29]; Buss[30]; Theunissen[31]; Feinberg[19]; Jaworska[22]
Capacity to develop sophisticated cognitive capacities Potential for such capacities (a "future like ours" or similar) grounds moral patienthood (or some status/enhancement). Stone[32]; Marquis[33][34]; Harman[35][36]; Steinbock[37]; Boonin[38]; Feinberg[19]; Wilkins[39]; McInerney[40]
Rudimentary cognitive capacities Lower the bar to sentience, interests, basic emotions, or consciousness as sufficient for (full) status. Wood and O'Neill[41]; Regan[42]; Singer[29]; DeGrazia[43][44]; Rachels[45]; Harman[36]; McMahan[20]; Taylor[46]; Naess[47]; Johnson[48]; Anderson[49]
Member of cognitively sophisticated species Moral patienthood via (i) being human or (ii) belonging to any cognitively sophisticated species/kind. Feinberg[19]; Dworkin[50]; Benn[51]; Cohen[52]; Scanlon[53]; Finnis[54]; Korsgaard[55]; Sumner[56]; McMahan[20]; McMahan[21]; Little[57]; Quinn[24]
Special relationships Strong reasons (akin to moral patienthood) grounded in species/community, parent–child, or other special ties. Nozick[58]; Scanlon[53]; Kittay[59]; Steinbock[37]; Quinn[24]; Warren[60]; Anderson[49]; Gilbert[61]; McMahan[62][20]
Incompletely realized sophisticated cognitive capacities Having such capacities incompletely realized (via mentor-guided activities/standards) can elevate status (possibly up to full moral patienthood). Jaworska & Tannenbaum[63]
Not being designed by anyone to fulfill any purpose The idea that an entity's not having been designed for a purpose grounds being treated as an end (and thus having moral status or some degree of it). Brennan[64]; Katz[65]
Naturalness (unaltered by humans) The claim that being natural or unaltered by human intervention confers intrinsic value and thus some moral status. Elliot[66]
Harmony and beauty (aesthetic value) of ecosystems Appeals to harmony, beauty, or aesthetic value of ecosystems (or nature generally) as grounds for moral considerability or status. Leopold (A Sand County Almanac)[67]; Callicott[68]

History

Moral patienthood may have existed since prehistory,[69][70] but most discussions of it as a distinct concept happened since the 1970s. News events where sources explicitly raised the issue of moral patienthood outside of philosophy are also added, except where they related to animals, since those are covered in the article "History of animal rights".

Before the 1970s

Philosophical writings from this period:

  • 1785: Immanuel Kant, Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals. Defines moral worth in terms of rational moral agency; denies that non-rational beings (including animals) have direct moral standing, framing duties to them as indirect duties to persons.
  • 1789: Jeremy Bentham, An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation. Pioneering utilitarian argument that the capacity to suffer, not rationality, should determine moral concern.
  • 1859: John Stuart Mill, On Liberty and Utilitarianism. Expands utilitarian moral consideration, though with less explicit focus than Bentham on nonhuman animals; articulates harm principle relevant to later patienthood debates.
  • 1892: Henry Sidgwick, The Methods of Ethics. Discusses impartiality and the moral point of view in a way that opens scope for nonhuman considerability, though still within a broadly human-centered framework.
  • 1930: C. D. Broad, Five Types of Ethical Theory. Clarifies distinctions between moral agents and those affected by their actions, laying groundwork for later "moral patient" terminology.
  • 1965: H.J. McCloskey, Rights. Argued that because animals lack moral self-determination and cannot claim rights, they lie outside the realm of direct moral rights.

In 1969, the Hastings Center for Bioethics was founded.[71]

1970s

Philosophical writings from this period:

  • 1972: Christopher D. Stone, "Should Trees Have Standing?—Toward Legal Rights for Natural Objects," Southern California Law Review. Landmarks the idea that nonhuman natural entities could be right-holders, catalyzing debates about direct standing (and hence patienthood) beyond humans and animals.
  • 1972: Michael Tooley, "Abortion and Infanticide," Philosophy & Public Affairs. Argues a right to life requires certain psychological capacities; uses fetal/infant cases to make moral status hinge on mental properties rather than species.
  • 1973: Mary Anne Warren, "On the Moral and Legal Status of Abortion," The Monist. Proposes personhood criteria (e.g., sentience, reasoning, self-awareness) to ground status claims in abortion ethics, modeling analytic treatment of "who counts."
  • 1974: Joel Feinberg, "The Rights of Animals and Unborn Generations," in Blackstone (ed.), Philosophy & Environmental Crisis. Connects interests to rights and explores whether animals and future people can be direct objects of duty—an influential frame for patienthood debates.
  • 1975: Peter Singer, Animal Liberation. Introduces the principle of equal consideration of interests and argues sentience (not species) grounds moral considerability—cementing animals as moral patients in utilitarian ethics.
  • 1977: Stephen R. L. Clark, The Moral Status of Animals. Early monograph squarely centering "moral status" language in analytic animal ethics, surveying grounds and implications.
  • 1978: Bonnie Steinbock, "Speciesism and the Idea of Equality," Philosophy. Defends limited species partiality against Singer-style equality, shaping later arguments about permissible asymmetries in status.
  • 1978: Kenneth E. Goodpaster, "On Being Morally Considerable," The Journal of Philosophy. Defends a life-based criterion: all living things are candidates for direct moral consideration, widening the domain of moral patients beyond sentients.

1980s

Philosophical writings from this period:

  • 1980: R. G. Frey, Interests and Rights: The Case Against Animals. A prominent restrictionist critique arguing animals lack the sorts of interests that could ground rights, sharpening contrasts with Singer/Regan.
  • 1983: Tom Regan, The Case for Animal Rights. Develops the moral agent / moral patient distinction and the subject-of-a-life criterion, arguing that many animals have inherent value and equal basic rights. Followed the § Narrow usage of the term "moral patient", which would be followed by some, but not all, sources.
  • 1986: Carl Cohen, "The Case for the Use of Animals in Biomedical Research," New England Journal of Medicine. Defends a contractarian-leaning view denying animals rights and thereby limiting their moral standing; a widely cited counterposition to Singer/Regan.
  • 1989: Don Marquis, "Why Abortion Is Immoral," The Journal of Philosophy. Offers the "future like ours" account of the wrongness of killing, thereby attributing strong moral status to early fetuses notwithstanding personhood doubts.

1990s

Philosophical writings from this period:

  • 1990: James Rachels, Created from Animals: The Moral Implications of Darwinism. Uses evolutionary considerations to erode sharp human/animal status boundaries, pressing consistency in our patienthood attributions.
  • 1996: David DeGrazia, Taking Animals Seriously: Mental Life and Moral Status. Systematically links empirical work on animal minds to degrees and kinds of moral standing; argues for robust direct considerability of many animals.
  • 1997: Mary Anne Warren, Moral Status: Obligations to Persons and Other Living Things. Offers a programmatic analytic account and plural criteria for status; helped standardize current usage of "moral status/considerability."
  • 1998: Gary E. Varner, In Nature's Interests? Interests, Animal Rights, and Environmental Ethics. Integrates animal ethics with environmental ethics via an interests-based framework, negotiating conflicts among different moral patients.

2000s

Philosophical writings from this period:

  • 2002: Jeff McMahan, The Ethics of Killing: Problems at the Margins of Life. Introduces the time-relative interest and two-tier ideas that nuance status and the wrongness of killing across embryos, fetuses, the severely cognitively disabled, and animals.
  • 2003: Nick Bostrom, Ethical Issues in Advanced Artificial Intelligence. Raises the question of artificial intelligence being a moral patient.
  • 2004: Alastair Norcross, "Puppies, Pigs, and People: Eating Meat and Marginal Cases," Philosophical Perspectives. Uses vivid marginal-case arguments to press moral parity between ordinary meat consumption and acts we clearly condemn, challenging status-based double standards.
  • 2004: Luciano Floridi & J. W. Sanders, "On the Morality of Artificial Agents," Minds and Machines. Distinguishes moral agency from moral patiency in computing/AI, explicitly treating artificial systems as potential moral patients as well as agents.
  • 2005: Eva Feder Kittay, "At the Margins of Moral Personhood," Ethics. From disability ethics, argues against capacity-threshold exclusions and for grounding full moral standing in relations of care and dependency.

2010s

Philosophical writings from this period:

  • 2012: David J. Gunkel, The Machine Question: Critical Perspectives on AI, Robots, and Ethics. Extends the patienthood debate to artificial entities, arguing that our moral community's boundaries may need to include sophisticated machines.
  • 2013 (rev. 2021/2025 updates): Agnieszka Jaworska & Julie Tannenbaum, "The Grounds of Moral Status," Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. A widely used analytic map of candidate grounds (sentience, agency, life, relationships, etc.) and the debate over full vs. graded moral status.
  • 2014: Agnieszka Jaworska & Julie Tannenbaum, "Person-Rearing Relationships as a Key to Higher Moral Status," Ethics. Defends a relational ground: the capacity to participate as a rearee in person-rearing relationships can elevate moral status above cognitively similar nonhumans.
  • 2014: David DeGrazia, "On the Moral Status of Infants and the Cognitively Disabled," Ethics. Critically assesses the person-rearing account and explores alternative explanations of higher status for some non-paradigm humans.
  • 2018: Christine M. Korsgaard, Fellow Creatures: Our Obligations to the Other Animals. A Kantian reconstruction grounding animals' moral standing as ends in themselves, challenging human exceptionalism within a deontological framework.
  • 2019: Shelly Kagan, How to Count Animals, More or Less. Defends a limited hierarchy of moral status (mostly graded), systematizing how status differences might affect the weight of interests across species.

2020s

In 2021, Open Philanthropy recommended a grant of $315,500 to "support research related to moral patienthood and moral weight."[72]

In 2022, Google engineer Blake Lemoine publicly claimed that LaMDA (a language model) was "sentient".[73][74]

Philosophical writings from this period:

  • 2021: Jamie Harris, Jacy Reese Anthis, The Moral Consideration of Artificial Entities: A Literature Review. Argue that there is wide agreement that some future artificial entities could warrant moral consideration, and that moral frameworks must be prepared.[75]
  • 2021: Vincent C. Müller, "Is it Time for Robot Rights? Moral Status in Artificial Entities," Ethics and Information Technology. Reviews when—and on what grounds—artificial systems might warrant moral status (and possibly rights), synthesizing recent AI-patienthood proposals.
  • 2021/2024: Lori Gruen & Susana Monsó, "The Moral Status of Animals," Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Up-to-date analytic survey of status theories as applied to nonhuman animals, covering rights, utilitarian, relational, and hybrid views.

See also

References

  1. ^ Haji, Ishtiyaque; Bernstein, Mark H. (November 2001). "On Moral Considerability: An Essay on Who Morally Matters". Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. 63 (3): 730. doi:10.2307/3071172. JSTOR 3071172.
  2. ^ Zhou, Xinyue; Guo, Siyuan; Huang, Rong; Ye, Weiling (2020), Wu, Shuang; Pantoja, Felipe; Krey, Nina (eds.), "Think versus Feel: Two Dimensions of Brand Anthropomorphism: An Abstract", Marketing Opportunities and Challenges in a Changing Global Marketplace, Cham: Springer International Publishing, pp. 351–352, doi:10.1007/978-3-030-39165-2_138, ISBN 978-3-030-39164-5, retrieved 2024-04-16
  3. ^ Danaher, John (March 2019). "The rise of the robots and the crisis of moral patiency". AI & Society. 34 (1): 129–136. doi:10.1007/s00146-017-0773-9. ISSN 0951-5666.
  4. ^ a b c d Audi, Robert, ed. (2015). The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy (3 ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/cbo9781139057509. ISBN 978-1-139-05750-9.
  5. ^ a b c d Jaworska, Agnieszka; Tannenbaum, Julie (2023), "The Grounds of Moral Status", in Zalta, Edward N.; Nodelman, Uri (eds.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2023 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 2024-04-16
  6. ^ a b Gruen, Lori; Monsó, Susana (2024), "The Moral Status of Animals", in Zalta, Edward N.; Nodelman, Uri (eds.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2024 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 2025-08-04
  7. ^ Moosavi, Parisa (2023-09-09). "Will intelligent machines become moral patients?". Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. 109 (1): 95–116. doi:10.1111/phpr.13019. ISSN 0031-8205.
  8. ^ Lan T, Sinhababu N, Carrasco LR (2022) Recognition of intrinsic values of sentient beings explains the sense of moral duty towards global nature conservation. PLoS ONE 17(10): e0276614. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0276614
  9. ^ Müller, N.D. (2022). Kantian Moral Concern, Love, and Respect. In: Kantianism for Animals. The Palgrave Macmillan Animal Ethics Series. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-01930-2_2
  10. ^ Balle, S.N. Empathic responses and moral status for social robots: an argument in favor of robot patienthood based on K. E. Løgstrup. AI & Soc 37, 535–548 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00146-021-01211-2
  11. ^ Harris, J., Anthis, J.R. The Moral Consideration of Artificial Entities: A Literature Review. Sci Eng Ethics 27, 53 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11948-021-00331-8
  12. ^ Taliaferro, Charles; Marty, Elsa J., eds. (2018). A dictionary of philosophy of religion (2nd ed.). New York: Bloomsbury Academic, An imprint of Bloomsbury Publishing Inc. ISBN 978-1-5013-2523-6.
  13. ^ a b Bunnin, Nicholas; Yu, Jiyuan (2004). The Blackwell dictionary of Western philosophy. Malden, MA: Blackwell Pub. ISBN 978-1-4051-0679-5.
  14. ^ Wadiwel, Dinesh Joseph (2015). The war against animals. Critical animal studies. Leiden; Boston: Brill. ISBN 978-90-04-30041-5.
  15. ^ "Animal Rights | Encyclopedia.com". www.encyclopedia.com. Retrieved 2024-04-16.
  16. ^ Floridi, Luciano; Sanders, J.W. (August 2004). "On the Morality of Artificial Agents". Minds and Machines. 14 (3): 349–379. doi:10.1023/B:MIND.0000035461.63578.9d. hdl:2299/1822. ISSN 0924-6495.
  17. ^ Quigley, Marian, ed. (2008). Encyclopedia of information ethics and security. Hershey: Information Science Reference. p. 516. ISBN 978-1-59140-987-8. OCLC 85444168.
  18. ^ Duff, Antony; Green, Stuart P., eds. (2011). Philosophical foundations of criminal law. Oxford; New York: Oxford University Press. p. 523. ISBN 978-0-19-955915-2.
  19. ^ a b c d Regan, Tom; Beauchamp, Tom L., eds. (1993). Matters of life and death: new introductory essays in moral philosophy (3 ed.). New York: Random House. pp. 98–104, 193, 197–198. ISBN 978-0-07-051330-3.
  20. ^ a b c d e McMahan, Jeff; MacMahan, Jeff (2003). The ethics of killing: problems at the margins of life. Oxford ethics series (1. iss. ... as paperback ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 45, 212–214, 216, 232, 235, 242, 225–226. ISBN 978-0-19-507998-2.
  21. ^ a b McMahan, Jeff (2008-01-01). "Challenges To Human Equality". The Journal of Ethics. 12 (1): 81–104. doi:10.1007/s10892-007-9020-9. ISSN 1572-8609.
  22. ^ a b c Jaworska, Agnieszka (2007). "Caring and Full Moral Standing". Ethics. 117 (3): 460–497. doi:10.1086/512780. ISSN 0014-1704. JSTOR 10.1086/512780.
  23. ^ Greenspan, Patricia (July 2010). "Making Room for Options: Moral Reasons, Imperfect Duties, and Choice". Social Philosophy and Policy. 27 (2): 181–205. doi:10.1017/S0265052509990203. ISSN 1471-6437.
  24. ^ a b c d Quinn, Warren (1984). "Abortion: Identity and Loss". Philosophy & Public Affairs. 13 (1): 24–54. ISSN 0048-3915. JSTOR 2265198.
  25. ^ Broome, John (1990). "Fairness". Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society. 91: 87–101. doi:10.1093/aristotelian/91.1.87. ISSN 0066-7374. JSTOR 4545128.
  26. ^ Bostrom, Nick (2024). Deep utopia: life and meaning in a solved world. Ideapress publishing. p. 81. ISBN 978-1-64687-164-3.
  27. ^ Korsgaard, Christine M.; Gregor, Mary; Timmermann, Jens (2012-04-19). Kant: Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals. pp. 428, 434, 436. doi:10.1017/cbo9780511919978. ISBN 978-1-107-00851-9. Retrieved 2025-08-13. {{cite book}}: |website= ignored (help)
  28. ^ TOOLEY, MICHAEL (2021-07-13), "Abortion and Infanticide", Rights and Wrongs of Abortion, Princeton University Press, p. 44, doi:10.2307/j.ctv1nxcvkr.6, ISBN 978-0-691-23316-1, retrieved 2025-08-13
  29. ^ a b Singer, Peter (1993-01-29). Practical Ethics. Cambridge University Press. pp. 95, 100. ISBN 978-0-521-43971-8.
  30. ^ Buss, Sarah (2012). "The Value of Humanity". The Journal of Philosophy. 109 (5/6): 352. doi:10.5840/jphil20121095/614. ISSN 0022-362X. JSTOR 43820709.
  31. ^ Theunissen, L. Nandi (2020). The Value of Humanity. Oxford University Press. pp. 126–127. ISBN 978-0-19-883264-5.
  32. ^ Stone, Jim (1987). "Why Potentiality Matters". Canadian Journal of Philosophy. 17 (4): 815–829. doi:10.1080/00455091.1987.10715920. ISSN 0045-5091. JSTOR 40231569.
  33. ^ Marquis, Don (Apr 1989). "Why abortion is immoral". The Journal of Philosophy. 86 (4): 183–202. doi:10.2307/2026961. ISSN 0022-362X. JSTOR 2026961. PMID 11782094.
  34. ^ Marquis, Don (1995). "Fetuses, Futures and Values". Southwest Philosophy Review. 11 (2): 263–265. doi:10.5840/swphilreview199511238. ISSN 0897-2346.
  35. ^ Harman, Elizabeth (1999). "Creation ethics: the moral status of early fetuses and the ethics of abortion". Philosophy & Public Affairs. 28 (4): 310–324. doi:10.1111/j.1088-4963.1999.00310.x. ISSN 0048-3915. PMID 11657937.
  36. ^ a b Harman, Elizabeth (May 2003). "The Potentiality Problem". Philosophical Studies. 114 (1–2): 187, 311. doi:10.1023/a:1024469419944. ISSN 0031-8116.
  37. ^ a b Steinbock, Bonnie (2011). Life before birth: the moral and legal status of embryos and fetuses (2nd ed.). New York Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 9, 13, 68–70. ISBN 978-0-19-534162-1.
  38. ^ Boonin, David (2002). A Defense of Abortion. Cambridge Studies in Philosophy and Public Policy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. pp. 46–49, 62, 84 & n.36, 48. doi:10.1017/cbo9780511610172. ISBN 978-0-521-52035-5.
  39. ^ Wilkins, B. T. (1993). "Does the fetus have a right to life?". Journal of Social Philosophy. 24 (1): 126–127. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9833.1993.tb00500.x. ISSN 0047-2786. PMID 16035157.
  40. ^ McInerney, Peter K. (May 1990). "Does a fetus already have a future-like-ours?". The Journal of Philosophy. 87 (5): 264–268. doi:10.2307/2026834. ISSN 0022-362X. JSTOR 2026834. PMID 11782096.
  41. ^ Wood, Allen W.; O'Neill, Onora (1998). "Kant on Duties Regarding Nonrational Nature". Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes. 72: 197. ISSN 0309-7013. JSTOR 4107017.
  42. ^ Regan, Tom (2004). The Case for Animal Rights. University of California Press. pp. 304, 324.
  43. ^ DeGrazia, David (1996). Taking Animals Seriously: Mental Life and Moral Status. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/cbo9781139172967. ISBN 978-0-521-56140-2.
  44. ^ DeGrazia, David (2008). "Moral Status As a Matter of Degree?". The Southern Journal of Philosophy. 46 (2): 181–198. doi:10.1111/j.2041-6962.2008.tb00075.x. ISSN 2041-6962.
  45. ^ Rachels, James (1990). Created From Animals: The Moral Implications of Darwinism. Oxford University Press. pp. 186–194.
  46. ^ Taylor, Paul W. (2011). Respect for nature: a theory of environmental ethics (25th anniversary ed.). Princeton: Princeton University Press. p. 75. ISBN 978-0-691-15024-6.
  47. ^ Naess, Arne (1986). "The Deep Ecological Movement". Philosophical Inquiry. 8 (1–2): 14. doi:10.5840/philinquiry198681/22.
  48. ^ Johnson, Lawrence E. (2000). A morally deep world: an essay on moral significance and environmental ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Pr. pp. 146, 148, 184, 287. ISBN 978-0-521-44706-5.
  49. ^ a b Sunstein, Cass R.; Nussbaum, Martha C. (2005-11-24). Animal Rights: Current Debates and New Directions. Oxford University Press. pp. 282–283, 284, 287–289. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780195305104.003.0014. ISBN 978-0-19-530510-4.
  50. ^ Dworkin, Ronald (2011). "3". Life's Dominion: An Argument about Abortion, Euthanasia, and Individual Freedom. Westminster: Knopf Doubleday Publishing Group. ISBN 978-0-679-73319-5.
  51. ^ Benn, S. (1967). "Egalitarianism and Equal Consideration of Interests". In Pennock, J. R.; Chapman, J. (eds.). Nomos IX: Equality. New York: Atherton Press. pp. 69–71.
  52. ^ Cohen, C. (1986-10-02). "The case for the use of animals in biomedical research". The New England Journal of Medicine. 315 (14): 865–870. doi:10.1056/NEJM198610023151405. ISSN 0028-4793. PMID 3748104.
  53. ^ a b Scanlon, Thomas (2000). What we owe to each other (1st ed.). Cambridge, Mass: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press. pp. 185–186. ISBN 978-0-674-00423-8.
  54. ^ Finnis, John (1995). "The Fragile Case for Euthanasia: A Reply to John Harris". In Keown, John (ed.). Euthanasia Examined: Ethical, Clinical and Legal Perspectives. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.
  55. ^ Korsgaard, Christine M. (2018-05-24). Fellow Creatures. Oxford Scholarship Online. Vol. 1. Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/oso/9780198753858.001.0001. ISBN 978-0-19-875385-8.
  56. ^ Sumner, L. W. (1981). Abortion and Moral Theory. Princeton University Press. pp. 97–101. doi:10.2307/j.ctt7zvdmc. JSTOR j.ctt7zvdmc.
  57. ^ Little, Margaret Olivia (2008). "Abortion and the Margins of Personhood". Rutgers Law Journal. 39: 332, 339–341, 348.
  58. ^ Nozick, Robert (2000). Socratic puzzles (3. print ed.). Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard Univ. Press. pp. 303–310. ISBN 978-0-674-81654-1.
  59. ^ Kittay, Eva Feder (2005). "At the Margins of Moral Personhood". Ethics. 116 (1): 100–131. doi:10.1086/454366. ISSN 0014-1704. JSTOR 10.1086/454366. PMID 16578953.
  60. ^ Warren, Mary Anne (1997). Moral status : obligations to persons and other living things. Internet Archive. Oxford : Clarendon Press. p. 176. ISBN 978-0-19-158815-0.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: publisher location (link)
  61. ^ Gilbert, Margaret (2018). Rights and Demands: A Foundational Inquiry. Oxford University Press. pp. 332, 341–342. ISBN 978-0-19-881376-7.
  62. ^ McMahan, Jeff (2005). "Our Fellow Creatures". The Journal of Ethics. 9 (3/4): 355. doi:10.1007/s10892-005-3512-2. ISSN 1382-4554. JSTOR 25115832.
  63. ^ Jaworska, Agnieszka; Tannenbaum, Julie (2014). "Person-Rearing Relationships as a Key to Higher Moral Status". Ethics. 124 (2): 242–271. doi:10.1086/673431. ISSN 0014-1704. JSTOR 10.1086/673431.
  64. ^ Brennan, Andrew; Center for Environmental Philosophy, The University of North Texas (1984). "The Moral Standing of Natural Objects". Environmental Ethics. 6 (1): 44, 56. doi:10.5840/enviroethics19846118. ISSN 0163-4275.
  65. ^ Katz, Eric (1997). Nature as Subject: Human Obligation and Natural Community. Bloomsbury Publishing PLC. pp. 129–131. ISBN 978-0-8476-8304-8.
  66. ^ Elliot, Robert, ed. (1997). Faking nature: the ethics of environmental restoration. Environmental philosophies series. London New York: Routledge. p. 80. ISBN 978-0-415-11140-9.
  67. ^ Leopold, Aldo (1972). A Sand county almanac and sketches here and there. New York usw: OUP. ISBN 978-0-19-500777-0.
  68. ^ Callicott, J. Baird; Center for Environmental Philosophy, The University of North Texas (1980). "Animal Liberation: A Triangular Affair". Environmental Ethics. 2 (4): 311–338. doi:10.5840/enviroethics19802424. ISSN 0163-4275.
  69. ^ Oestigaard, Terje (2021-06-10). "Prehistoric Ethics". Current Swedish Archaeology. 26 (1): 65–70. doi:10.37718/csa.2016.06. ISSN 2002-3901.
  70. ^ Gordijn, Bert; ten Have, Henk (2021-09-01). "Ethical (mis)use of prehistory". Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy. 24 (3): 303–304. doi:10.1007/s11019-021-10041-4. ISSN 1572-8633. PMID 34241744.
  71. ^ Committee, The Hastings Center Bioethics Timeline. "The Hastings Center Bioethics Timeline". The Hastings Center for Bioethics. Retrieved 2025-08-14.
  72. ^ Open Philanthropy (March 2021). "Rethink Priorities — Moral Patienthood and Moral Weight Research". Retrieved December 1, 2023.
  73. ^ Tiku, Nitasha (June 11, 2022). "The Google engineer who thinks the company's AI has come to life". The Washington Post. ISSN 0190-8286. Archived from the original on June 11, 2022. Retrieved June 12, 2022.
  74. ^ Luscombe, Richard (June 12, 2022). "Google engineer put on leave after saying AI chatbot has become sentient". The Guardian. ISSN 0261-3077. Archived from the original on June 12, 2022. Retrieved June 18, 2022.
  75. ^ Harris, Jamie; Anthis, Jacy Reese (2021-08-09). "The Moral Consideration of Artificial Entities: A Literature Review". Science and Engineering Ethics. 27 (4): 53. doi:10.1007/s11948-021-00331-8. ISSN 1471-5546. PMC 8352798. PMID 34370075.